זוהי גירסת HTML של הקובץ http://www.ffst.hr/~logika/2006filozofijaznanosti/carnap.pdf.
G o o g l e יוצרת גרסאות html של קבצים באופן אוטומטי בזמן שאנו סורקים את האינטרנט.
לקשר דף זה או להוסיפו למועדפים, השתמש בבכתובת האתר הבאה: http://www.google.com/search?q=cache:SaQ6X3F5N4YJ:www.ffst.hr/~logika/2006filozofijaznanosti/carnap.pdf+toovy+teavy&hl=iw&gl=il&ct=clnk&cd=1


Google אינה קשורה למחברי דף זה ואיננה אחראית לתוכנו.
מילות חיפוש אלו הודגשו:  toovy  teavy 

Page 1
Publication Information:
Book Title: Logical Positivism.
Contributors: A. J. Ayer - editor.
Publisher: Free Press. Place of Publication: New York.
Publication Year: 1959.
pp. 60—81
3
The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical
Analysis of Language
1
By RUDOLF CARNAP
(TRANSLATED BY ARTHUR PAP)
1. INTRODUCTION
THERE HAVE BEEN many opponents of metaphysics from the Greek skeptics to the
empiricists of the 19th century. Criticisms of very diverse kinds have been set forth. Many have
declared that the doctrine of metaphysics is false, since it contradicts our empirical knowledge.
Others have believed it to be uncertain, on the ground that its problems transcend the limits of
human knowledge. Many antimetaphysicians have declared that occupation with metaphysical
questions is sterile. Whether or not these questions can be answered, it is at any rate unnecessary
to worry about them; let us devote ourselves entirely to the practical tasks which confront active
men every day of their lives!
The development of modern logic has made it possible to give a new and sharper answer to
the question of the validity and justification of metaphysics. The researches of applied logic or
the theory of knowledge, which aim at clarifying the cognitive content of scientific statements
and thereby the meanings of the terms that occur in the statements, by means of logical
analysis, lead to a positive and to a negative result. The positive result is worked out in the
domain of empirical science; the various concepts of the various branches of science are
clarified; their formal-logical and epistemological connections are made explicit. In the domain
of metaphysics, including all philosophy of value and normative theory, logical analysis yields
1
This article, originally entitled "Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache", appeared in
Erkenntnis, Vol. II ( 1932). It is published here with the kind permission of Professor Carnap.

Page 2
the negative result that the alleged statements in this domain are entirely meaningless.
Therewith a radical elimination of metaphysics is attained, which was not yet possible from the
earlier antimetaphysical standpoints. It is true that related ideas may be found already in several
earlier trains of thought, e.g. those of a nominalistic kind; but it is only now when the
development of logic during recent decades provides us with a sufficiently sharp tool that the
decisive step can be taken.
In saying that the so-called statements of metaphysics are meaningless, we intend this word
in its strictest sense. In a loose sense of the word a statement or a question is at times called
meaningless if it is entirely sterile to assert or ask it. We might say this for instance about the
question "what is the average weight of those inhabitants of Vienna whose telephone number
ends with '3'?" or about a statement which is quite obviously false like "in 1910 Vienna had 6
inhabitants" or about a statement which is not just empirically, but logically false, a
contradictory statement such as "persons A and B are each a year older than the other." Such
sentences are really meaningful, though they are pointless or false; for it is only meaningful
sentences that are even divisible into (theoretically) fruitful and sterile, true and false. In the
strict sense, however, a sequence of words is meaningless if it does not, within a specified
language, constitute a statement. It may happen that such a sequence of words looks like a
statement at first glance; in that case we call it a pseudostatement. Our thesis, now, is that
logical analysis reveals the alleged statements of metaphysics to be pseudo-statements.
A language consists of a vocabulary and a syntax, i.e. a set of words which have meanings
and rules of sentence formation. These rules indicate how sentences may be formed out of the
various sorts of words. Accordingly, there are two kinds of pseudo-statements: either they
contain a word which is erroneously believed to have meaning, or the constituent words are
meaningful, yet are put together in a counter-syntactical way, so that they do not yield a
meaningful statement. We shall show in terms of examples that pseudo-statements of both
kinds occur in metaphysics. Later we shall have to inquire into the reasons that support our
contention that metaphysics in its entirety consists of such pseudo-statements.
2. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF A WORD
A word which (within a definite language) has a meaning, is usually also said to designate a
concept; if it only seems to have a meaning while it really does not, we speak of a "pseudo-
concept." How is the origin of a pseudo-concept to be explained? Has not every word been
introduced into the language for no other purpose than to express something or other, so that it
had a definite meaning from the very beginning of its use? How, then, can a traditional language
contain meaningless words? To be sure, originally every word (excepting rare cases which we
shall illustrate later) had a meaning. In the course of historical development a word frequently
changes its meaning. And it also happens at times that a word loses its old sense without
acquiring a new one. It is thus that a pseudo-concept arises.What, now, is the meaning of a word?
What stipulations concerning a word must be made in order for it to be significant? (It does not
matter for our investigation whether these stipulations are explicitly laid down, as in the case of
some words and symbols of modern science, or whether they have been tacitly agreed upon, as is
the case for most words of traditional language.) First, the syntax of the word must be fixed, i.e.
the mode of its occurrence in the simplest sentence form in which it is capable of occurring; we
call this sentence form its elementary sentence. The elementary sentence form for the word
"stone" e.g. is "x is a stone"; in sentences of this form some designation from the category of
things occupies the place of "x," e.g. "this diamond," "this apple." Secondly, for an elementary

Page 3
sentence S containing the word an answer must be given to the following question, which can be
formulated in various ways:
1. What sentences is S deducible from, and what sentences are deducible from S?
2. Under what conditions is S supposed to be true, and under what conditions false?
3. How is S to be verified?
4. What is the meaning of S?
(1) is the correct formulation; formulation (2) accords with the phraseology of logic, (3) with
the phraseology of the theory of knowledge, (4) with that of philosophy (phenomenology).
Wittgenstein has asserted that (2) expresses what philosophers mean by (4): the meaning of a
sentence consists in its truth-condition. ((1) is the "metalogical" formulation; it is planned to
give elsewhere a detailed exposition of metalogic as the theory of syntax and meaning, i.e.
relations of deducibility.)
In the case of many words, specifically in the case of the overwhelming majority of scientific
words, it is possible to specify their meaning by reduction to other words ("constitution,"
definition).
E.g. "'arthropodes' are animals with segmented bodies and jointed legs." Thereby the above-
mentioned question for the elementary sentence form of the word "arthropode," that is for the
sentence form "the thing x is an arthropode," is answered: it has been stipulated that a sentence
of this form is deducible from premises of the form "x is an animal," "x has a segmented body,"
"x has jointed legs," and that conversely each of these sentences is deducible from the former
sentence. By means of these stipulations about deducibility (in other words: about the truth-
condition, about the method of verification, about the meaning) of the elementary sentence
about "arthropode" the meaning of the word "arthropode" is fixed. In this way every word of
the language is reduced to other words and finally to the words which occur in the so-called
"observation sentences" or "protocol sentences." It is through this reduction that the word
acquires its meaning.
For our purposes we may ignore entirely the question concerning the content and form of the
primary sentences (protocol sentences) which has not yet been definitely settled. In the theory
of knowledge it is customary to say that the primary sentences refer to "the given"; but there is
no unanimity on the question what it is that is given. At times the position is taken that
sentences about the given speak of the simplest qualities of sense and feeling (e.g. "warm,"
"blue," "joy" and so forth); others incline to the view that basic sentences refer to total
experiences and similarities between them; a still different view has it that even the basic
sentences speak of things. Regardless of this diversity of opinion it is certain that a sequence of
words has a meaning only if its relations of deducibility to the protocol sentences are fixed,
whatever the characteristics of the protocol sentences may be; and similarly, that a word is
significant only if the sentences in which it may occur are reducible to protocol sentences.
Since the meaning of a word is determined by its criterion of application (in other words: by
the relations of deducibility entered into by its elementary sentence-form, by its truth-
conditions, by the method of its verification), the stipulation of the criterion takes away one's
freedom to decide what one wishes to "mean" by the word. If the word is to receive an exact

Page 4
meaning, nothing less than the criterion of application must be given; but one cannot, on the
other hand, give more than the criterion of application, for the latter is a sufficient
determination of meaning. The meaning is implicitly contained in the criterion; all that remains
to be done is to make the meaning explicit.
Let us suppose, by way of illustration, that someone invented the new word "teavy" and
maintained that there are things which are teavy and things which are not teavy. In order to
learn the meaning of this word, we ask him about its criterion of application: how is one to
ascertain in a concrete case whether a given thing is teavy or not? Let us suppose to begin with
that we get no answer from him: there are no empirical signs of teavyness, he says. In that case
we would deny the legitimacy of using this word. If the person who uses the word says that all
the same there are things which are teavy and there are things which are not teavy, only it
remains for the weak, finite intellect of man an eternal secret which things are teavy and which
are not, we shall regard this as empty verbiage. But perhaps he will assure us that he means,
after all, something by the word "teavy." But from this we only learn the psychological fact that
he associates some kind of images and feelings with the word. The word does not acquire a
meaning through such associations. If no criterion of application for the word is stipulated, then
nothing is asserted by the sentences in which it occurs, they are but pseudo-
statements.Secondly, take the case when we are given a criterion of application for a new word,
say "toovy"; in particular, let the sentence "this thing is toovy" be true if and only if the thing is
quadrangular (It is irrelevant in this context whether the criterion is explicitly stated or whether
we derive it by observing the affirmative and the negative uses of the word). Then we will say:
the word "toovy" is synonymous with the word "quadrangular." And we will not allow its users
to tell us that nevertheless they "intended" something else by it than "quadrangular"; that
though every quadrangular thing is also toovy and conversely, this is only because
quadrangularity is the visible manifestation of toovyness, but that the latter itself is a hidden,
not itself observable property. We would reply that after the criterion of application has been
fixed, the synonymy of "toovy" and "quadrangular" is likewise fixed, and that we are no further
at liberty to "intend" this or that by the word.Let us briefly summarize the result of our analysis.
Let "a" be any word and "S(a)" the elementary sentence in which it occurs. Then the sufficient
and necessary condition for "a" being meaningful may be given by each of the following
formulations, which ultimately say the same thing:
1. The empirical criteria for a are known.
2. It has been stipulated from what protocol sentences "S(a)" is deducible.
3. The truth-conditions for "S(a)" are fixed.
4. The method of verification of "S(a)" is known. 2
3. METAPHYSICAL WORDS WITHOUT MEANING
Many words of metaphysics, now, can be shown not to fulfill the above requirement, and
therefore to be devoid of meaning.
2
For the logical and epistemological conception which underlies our exposition, but can only briefly be intimated here,
cf. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 1922, and Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 1928.

Page 5
Let us take as an example the metaphysical term "principle" (in the sense of principle of being,
not principle of knowledge or axiom). Various metaphysicians offer an answer to the question
which is the (highest) "principle of the world" (or of "things," of "existence," of "being"), e.g.
water, number, form, motion, life, the spirit, the idea, the unconscious, activity, the good, and so
forth. In order to discover the meaning of the word "principle" in this metaphysical question we
must ask the metaphysician under what conditions a statement of the form "x is the principle of
y" would be true and under what conditions it would be false. In other words: we ask for the
criteria of application or for the definition of the word "principle." The metaphysician replies
approximately as follows: "x is the principle of y" is to mean "y arises out of x," "the being of y
rests on the being of x," "y exists by virtue of x" and so forth. But these words are ambiguous and
vague. Frequently they have a clear meaning; e.g., we say of a thing or process y that it "arises
out of" x when we observe that things or processes of kind x are frequently or invariably followed
by things or processes of kind y (causal connection in the sense of a lawful succession). But the
metaphysician tells us that he does not mean this empirically observable relationship. For in that
case his metaphysical theses would be merely empirical propositions of the same kind as those of
physics. The expression "arising from" is not to mean here a relation of temporal and causal
sequence, which is what the word ordinarily means. Yet, no criterion is specified for any other
meaning. Consequently, the alleged "metaphysical" meaning, which the word is supposed to have
here in contrast to the mentioned empirical meaning, does not exist. If we reflect on the original
meaning of the word "principium" (and of the corresponding Greek word αρχἤ"), we notice the
same development. The word is explicitly deprived of its original meaning "beginning"; it is not
supposed to mean the temporally prior any more, but the prior in some other, specifically
metaphysical, respect. The criteria for this "metaphysical respect," however, are lacking. In both
cases, then, the word has been deprived of its earlier meaning without being given a new
meaning; there remains the word as an empty shell. From an earlier period of significant use, it is
still associatively connected with various mental images; these in turn get associated with new
mental images and feelings in the new context of usage. But the word does not thereby become
meaningful; and it remains meaningless as long as no method of verification can be described.
Another example is the word "God." Here we must, apart from the variations of its usage
within each domain, distinguish the linguistic usage in three different contexts or historical
epochs, which however overlap temporally. In its mythological use the word has a clear
meaning. It, or parallel words in other languages, is sometimes used to denote physical beings
which are enthroned on Mount Olympus, in Heaven or in Hades, and which are endowed with
power, wisdom, goodness and happiness to a greater or lesser extent. Sometimes the word also
refers to spiritual beings which, indeed, do not have manlike bodies, yet manifest themselves
nevertheless somehow in the things or processes of the visible world and are therefore
empirically verifiable. In its metaphysical use, on the other hand, the word "God" refers to
something beyond experience. The word is deliberately divested of its reference to a physical
being or to a spiritual being that is immanent in the physical. And as it is not given a new
meaning, it becomes meaningless. To be sure, it often looks as though the word "God" had a
meaning even in metaphysics. But the definitions which are set up prove on closer inspection to
be pseudo-definitions. They lead either to logically illegitimate combinations of words (of
which we shall treat later) or to other metaphysical words (e.g. "primordial basis," "the
absolute," "the unconditioned," "the autonomous," "the self-dependent" and so forth), but in no
case to the truth-conditions of its elementary sentences. In the case of this word not even the
first requirement of logic is met, that is the requirement to specify its syntax, i.e. the form of its
occurrence in elementary sentences. An elementary sentence would here have to be of the form
"x is a God"; yet, the metaphysician either rejects this form entirely without substituting
another, or if he accepts it he neglects to indicate the syntactical category of the variable x.

Page 6
(Categories are, for example, material things, properties of things, relations between things,
numbers etc.).
The theological usage of the word "God" falls between its mythological and its metaphysical
usage. There is no distinctive meaning here, but an oscillation from one of the mentioned two
uses to the other. Several theologians have a clearly empirical (in our terminology,
"mythological") concept of God. In this case there are no pseudo-statements; but the
disadvantage for the theologian lies in the circumstance that according to this interpretation the
statements of theology are empirical and hence are subject to the judgment of empirical
science. The linguistic usage of other theologians is clearly metaphysical. Others again do not
speak in any definite way, whether this is because they follow now this, now that linguistic
usage, or because they express themselves in terms whose usage is not clearly classifiable since
it tends towards both sides.Just like the examined examples "principle" and "God," most of the
other specifically metaphysical terms are devoid of meaning, e.g. "the Idea," "the Absolute,"
"the Unconditioned," "the Infinite," "the being of being," "non-being," "thing in itself,"
"absolute spirit," "objective spirit," "essence," "being-in-itself," "being-in-and-foritself,"
"emanation," "manifestation," "articulation," "the Ego," "the non-Ego," etc. These expressions
are in the same boat with "teavy," our previously fabricated example. The metaphysician tells
us that empirical truth-conditions cannot be specified; if he adds that nevertheless he "means"
something, we know that this is merely an allusion to associated images and feelings which,
however, do not bestow a meaning on the word. The alleged statements of metaphysics which
contain such words have no sense, assert nothing, are mere pseudo-statements. Into the
explanation of their historical origin we shall inquire later.
4. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF A SENTENCE
So far we have considered only those pseudo-statements which contain a meaningless word.
But there is a second kind of pseudostatement. They consist of meaningful words, but the words
are put together in such a way that nevertheless no meaning results. The syntax of a language
specifies which combinations of words are admissible and which inadmissible. The grammatical
syntax of natural languages, however, does not fulfill the task of elimination of senseless
combinations of words in all cases. Let us take as examples the following sequences of words:
1. " Caesar is and"
2. " Caesar is a prime number"
The word sequence (1) is formed countersyntactically; the rules of syntax require that the
third position be occupied, not by a conjunction, but by a predicate, hence by a noun (with
article) or by an adjective. The word sequence "Caesar is a general," e.g., is formed in
accordance with the rules of syntax. It is a meaningful word sequence, a genuine sentence. But,
now, word sequence (2) is likewise syntactically correct, for it has the same grammatical form
as the sentence just mentioned. Nevertheless (2) is meaningless. "Prime number" is a predicate
of numbers; it can be neither affirmed nor denied of a person. Since (2) looks like a statement
yet is not a statement, does not assert anything, expresses neither a true nor a false proposition,
we call this word sequence a "pseudo-statement." The fact that the rules of grammatical syntax
are not violated easily seduces one at first glance into the erroneous opinion that one still has to
do with a statement, albeit a false one. But "a is a prime number" is false if and only if a is
divisible by a natural number different from a and from 1; evidently it is illicit to put here
"Caesar" for "a." This example has been so chosen that the nonsense is easily detectable. Many

Page 7
so-called statements of metaphysics are not so easily recognized to be pseudo-statements. The
fact that natural languages allow the formation of meaningless sequences of words without
violating the rules of grammar, indicates that grammatical syntax is, from a logical point of
view, inadequate. If grammatical syntax corresponded exactly to logical syntax, pseudo-
statements could not arise. If grammatical syntax differentiated not only the wordcategories of
nouns, adjectives, verbs, conjunctions etc., but within each of these categories made the further
distinctions that are logically indispensable, then no pseudo-statements could be formed. If,
e.g., nouns were grammatically subdivided into several kinds of words, according as they
designated properties of physical objects, of numbers etc., then the words "general" and "prime
number" would belong to grammatically different word-categories, and (2) would be just as
linguistically incorrect as (1). In a correctly constructed language, therefore, all nonsensical
sequences of words would be of the kind of example (1). Considerations of grammar would
already eliminate them as it were automatically; i.e. in order to avoid nonsense, it would be
unnecessary to pay attention to the meanings of the individual words over and above their
syntactical type (their "syntactical category," e.g. thing, property of things, relation between
things, number, property of numbers, relation between numbers, and so forth). It follows that if
our thesis that the statements of metaphysics are pseudo-statements is justifiable, then
metaphysics could not even be expressed in a logically constructed language. This is the great
philosophical importance of the task, which at present occupies the logicians, of building a
logical syntax.
5. METAPHYSICAL PSEUDO-STATEMENTS
Let us now take a look at some examples of metaphysical pseudostatements of a kind where
the violation of logical syntax is especially obvious, though they accord with historical-
grammatical syntax. We select a few sentences from that metaphysical school which at present
exerts the strongest influence in Germany. 3
"What is to be investigated is being only and--nothing else; being alone and further--nothing;
solely being, and beyond being-nothing. What about this Nothing? . . . Does the Nothing exist
only because the Not, i.e. the Negation, exists? Or is it the other way around? Does Negation
and the Not exist only because the Nothing exists? . . . We assert: the Nothing is prior to the
Not and the Negation. . . . Where do we seek the Nothing? How do we find the Nothing. . . .
We know the Nothing. . . . Anxiety reveals the Nothing. . . . That for which and because of
which we were anxious, was 'really'--nothing. Indeed: the Nothing itself--as such--was present.
. . . What about this Nothing?--The Nothing itself nothings."
In order to show that the possibility of forming pseudo-statements is based on a logical
defect of language, we set up the schema below. The sentences under I are grammatically as
well as logically impeccable, hence meaningful. The sentences under II (excepting B3) are in
grammatical respects perfectly analogous to those under I. Sentence form IIA (as question and
answer) does not, indeed, satisfy the requirements to be imposed on a logically correct
language. But it is nevertheless meaningful, because it is translatable into correct language.
This is shown by sentence IIIA, which has the same meaning as IIA. Sentence form IIA then
proves to be undesirable because we can be led from it, by means of grammatically faultless
operations, to the meaningless sentence forms IIB, which are taken from the above quotation.
3
The following quotations (original italics) are taken from M. Heidegger, Was 1st Metaphysik? 1929. We could just as
well have selected passages from any other of the numerous metaphysicians of the present or of the past; yet the
selected passages seem to us to illustrate our thesis especially well.

Page 8
These forms cannot even be constructed in the correct language of Column III. Nonetheless,
their nonsensicality is not obvious at first glance, because one is easily deceived by the analogy
with the meaningful sentences IB. The fault of our language identified here lies, therefore, in
the circumstance that, in contrast to a logically correct language, it admits of the same
grammatical form for meaningful and meaningless word sequences. To each sentence in words
we have added a corresponding formula in the notation of symbolic logic; these formulae
facilitate recognition of the undesirable analogy between IA and IIA and therewith of the origin
of the meaningless constructions IIB.
I.
II.
III.
Transition from
Meaningful
Sense to
Sentences of
Nonsense in
Logically
Ordinary
Ordinary
Correct
Language
Language
Language
A. What is outside?
A. What is outside?
A. There is nothing
OU(?)
Ou(?)
(does not exist any-
Rain is outside
Nothing is outside
thing) which is
Ou(r)
Ou(no)
outside.
∼(∃x).Ou(x)
B. What about this rain?
B. "What about this
B. None of these forms
(i.e. what does the
Nothing?" ?(no)
can even be
rain do? or:
what constructed.
else can be said
about this rain?
?(r)
1. We know the rain
1. "We seek the
K(r)
Nothing"
"We find the
Nothing"
"We know the
Nothing"
K(no)
2. The rain rains
2. "The Nothing

Page 9
R(r)
nothings"
No(no)
3. "The Nothing
exists only
because . . ."
Ex(no)
On closer inspection of the pseudo-statements under IIB, we also find some differences. The
construction of sentence (1) is simply based on the mistake of employing the word "nothing" as
a noun, because it is customary in ordinary language to use it in this form in order to construct
a negative existential statement (see IIA). In a correct language, on the other hand, it is not a
particular name, but a certain logical form of the sentence that serves this purpose (see IIIA).
Sentence IIB2 adds something new, viz. the fabrication of the meaningless word "to nothing."
This sentence, therefore, is senseless for a twofold reason. We pointed out before that the
meaningless words of metaphysics usually owe their origin to the fact that a meaningful word is
deprived of its meaning through its metaphorical use in metaphysics. But here we confront one
of those rare cases where a new word is introduced which never had a meaning to begin with.
Likewise sentence IIB3 must be rejected for two reasons. In respect of the error of using the
word "nothing" as a noun, it is like the previous sentences. But in addition it involves a
contradiction. For even if it were admissible to introduce "nothing" as a name or description of
an entity, still the existence of this entity would be denied in its very definition, whereas
sentence (3) goes on to affirm its existence. This sentence, therefore, would be contradictory,
hence absurd, even if it were not already meaningless.
In view of the gross logical errors which we find in sentences IIB, we might be led to
conjecture that perhaps the word "nothing" has in Heidegger's treatise a meaning entirely
different from the customary one. And this presumption is further strengthened as we go on to
read there that anxiety reveals the Nothing, that the Nothing itself is present as such in anxiety.
For here the word "nothing" seems to refer to a certain emotional constitution, possibly of a
religious sort, or something or other that underlies such emotions. If such were the case, then
the mentioned logical errors in sentences IIB would not be committed. But the first sentence of
the quotation at the beginning of this section proves that this interpretation is not possible. The
combination of "only" and "nothing else" shows unmistakably that the word "nothing" here has
the usual meaning of a logical particle that serves for the formulation of a negative existential
statement. This introduction of the word "nothing" is then immediately followed by the leading
question of the treatise: "What about this Nothing?".
But our doubts as to a possible misinterpretation get completely dissolved as we note that the
author of the treatise is clearly aware of the conflict between his questions and statements, and
logic. "Question and answer in regard to the Nothing are equally absurd in themselves. . . . The
fundamental rule of thinking commonly appealed to, the law of prohibited contradiction,
general 'logic,' destroys this question." All the worse for logic! We must abolish its
sovereignty: "If thus the power of the understanding in the field of questions concerning
Nothing and Being is broken, then the fate of the sovereignty of 'logic' within philosophy is
thereby decided as well. The very idea of 'logic' dissolves in the whirl of a more basic
questioning." But will sober science condone the whirl of counterlogical questioning? To this
question too there is a ready answer: "The alleged sobriety and superiority of science becomes
ridiculous if it does not take the Nothing seriously." Thus we find here a good confirmation of

Page 10
our thesis; a metaphysician himself here states that his questions and answers are irreconcilable
with logic and the scientific way of thinking.
The difference between our thesis and that of the earlier antimetaphysicians should now be
clear. We do not regard metaphysics as "mere speculation" or "fairy tales." The statements of a
fairy tale do not conflict with logic, but only with experience; they are perfectly meaningful,
although false. Metaphysics is not "superstition"; it is possible to believe true and false
propositions, but not to believe meaningless sequences of words. Metaphysical statements are
not even acceptable as "working hypotheses"; for an hypothesis must be capable of entering
into relations of deducibility with (true or false) empirical statements, which is just what
pseudo-statements cannot do.
With reference to the so-called limitation of human knowledge an attempt is sometimes made
to save metaphysics by raising the following objection: metaphysical statements are not,
indeed, verifiable by man nor by any other finite being; nevertheless they might be construed as
conjectures about the answers which a being with higher or even perfect powers of knowledge
would make to our questions, and as such conjectures they would, after all, be meaningful. To
counter this objection, let us consider the following. If the meaning of a word cannot be
specified, or if the sequence of words does not accord with the rules of syntax, then one has not
even asked a question. (Just think of the pesudo-questions: "Is this table teavy?", "is the number
7 holy?", "which numbers are darker, the even or the odd ones?"). Where there is no question,
not even an omniscient being can give an answer. Now the objector may say: just as one who
can see may communicate new knowledge to the blind, so a higher being might perhaps
communicate to us metaphysical knowledge, e.g. whether the visible world is the manifestation
of a spirit. Here we must reflect on the meaning of "new knowledge." It is, indeed, conceivable
that we might encounter animals who tell us about a new sense. If these beings were to prove to
us Fermat's theorem or were to invent a new physical instrument or were to establish a hitherto
unknown law of nature, then our knowledge would be increased with their help. For this sort of
thing we can test, just the way even a blind man can understand and test the whole of physics
(and therewith any statement made by those who can see). But if those hypothetical beings tell
us something which we cannot verify, then we cannot understand it either; in that case no
information has been communicated to us, but mere verbal sounds devoid of meaning though
possibly associated with images. It follows that our knowledge can only be quantitatively
enlarged by other beings, no matter whether they know more or less or everything, but no
knowledge of an essentially different kind can be added. What we do not know for certain, we
may come to know with greater certainty through the assistance of other beings; but what is
unintelligible, meaningless for us, cannot become meaningful through someone else's
assistance, however vast his knowledge might be. Therefore no god and no devil can give us
metaphysical knowledge.
6. MEANINGLESSNESS OF ALL METAPHYSICS
The examples of metaphysical statements which we have analyzed were all taken from just one
treatise. But our results apply with equal validity, in part even in verbally identical ways, to
other metaphysical systems. That treatise is completely in the right in citing approvingly a
statement by Hegel ("pure Being and pure Nothing, therefore, are one and the same"). The
metaphysics of Hegel has exactly the same logical character as this modern system of
metaphysics. And the same holds for the rest of the metaphysical systems, though the kind of
phraseology and therewith the kind of logical errors that occur in them deviate more or less
from the kind that occurs in the examples we discussed.

Page 11
It should not be necessary here to adduce further examples of specific metaphysical sentences
in diverse systems and submit them to analysis. We confine ourselves to an indication of the
most frequent kinds of errors.
Perhaps the majority of the logical mistakes that are committed when pseudo-statements are
made, are based on the logical faults infecting the use of the word "to be" in our language (and
of the corresponding words in other languages, at least in most European languages). The first
fault is the ambiguity of the word "to be." It is sometimes used as copula prefixed to a predicate
("I am hungry"), sometimes to designate existence ("I am"). This mistake is aggravated by the
fact that metaphysicians often are not clear about this ambiguity. The second fault lies in the
form of the verb in its second meaning, the meaning of existence. The verbal form feigns a
predicate where there is none. To be sure, it has been known for a long time that existence is
not a property (cf. Kant's refutation of the ontological proof of the existence of God). But it was
not until the advent of modern logic that full consistency on this point was reached: the
syntactical form in which modern logic introduces the sign for existence is such that it cannot,
like a predicate, be applied to signs for objects, but only to predicates (cf. e.g. sentence IIIa in
the above table). Most metaphysicians since antiquity have allowed themselves to be seduced
into pseudo-statements by the verbal, and therewith the predicative form of the word "to be,"
e.g. "I am," "God is."
We meet an illustration of this error in Descartes' "cogito, ergo sum." Let us disregard here the
material objections that have been raised against the premise--viz. whether the sentence "I
think" adequately expresses the intended state of affairs or contains perhaps an hypostasis--and
consider the two sentences only from the formallogical point of view. We notice at once two
essential logical mistakes. The first lies in the conclusion "I am." The verb "to be" is
undoubtedly meant in the sense of existence here; for a copula cannot be used without
predicate; indeed, Descartes' "I am" has always been interpreted in this sense. But in that case
this sentence violates the above-mentioned logical rule that existence can be predicated only in
conjunction with a predicate, not in conjunction with a name (subject, proper name). An
existential statement does not have the form "a exists" (as in "I am," i.e. "I exist"), but "there
exists something of such and such a kind." The second error lies in the transition from "I think"
to "I exist." If from the statement "P(a)" ("a has the property P") an existential statement is to
be deduced, then the latter can assert existence only with respect to the predicate P, not with
respect to the subject a of the premise. What follows from "I am a European" is not "I exist,"
but "a European exists." What follows from "I think" is not "I am" but "there exists something
that thinks."
The circumstance that our languages express existence by a verb ('to be" or "to exist") is not in
itself a logical fault; it is only inappropriate, dangerous. The verbal form easily misleads us into
the misconception that existence is a predicate. One then arrives at such logically incorrect and
hence senseless modes of expression as were just examined. Likewise such forms as "Being" or
"Not-Being," which from time immemorial have played a great role in metaphysics, have the
same origin. In a logically correct language such forms cannot even be constructed. It appears
that in the Latin and the German languages the forms "ens" or "das Seiende" were, perhaps
under the seductive influence of the Greek example, introduced specifically for use by
metaphysicians; in this way the language deteriorated logically whereas the addition was
believed to represent an improvement.
Another very frequent violation of logical syntax is the so-called "type confusion" of concepts.
While the previously mentioned mistake consists in the predicative use of a symbol with non-

Page 12
predicative meaning, in this case a predicate is, indeed, used as predicate yet as predicate of a
different type. We have here a violation of the rules of the so-called theory of types. An
artificial example is the sentence we discussed earlier: "Caesar is a prime number." Names of
persons and names of numbers belong to different logical types, and so do accordingly
predicates of persons (e.g. "general") and predicates of numbers ("prime number"). The error of
type confusion is, unlike the previously discussed usage of the verb "to be," not the prerogative
of metaphysics but already occurs very often in conversational language also. But here it rarely
leads to nonsense. The typical ambiguity of words is here of such a kind that it can be easily
removed.
Example: 1. "This table is larger than that." 2. "The height of this table is larger than the height
of that table." Here the word "larger" is used in (1) for a relation between objects, in (2) for a
relation between numbers, hence for two distinct syntactical categories. The mistake is here
unimportant; it could, e.g., be eliminated by writing "larger1" and "larger2"; "larger1" is then
defined in terms of "larger2" by declaring statement form (1) to be synonymous with (2) (and
others of a similar kind).
Since the confusion of types causes no harm in conversational language, it is usually ignored
entirely. This is, indeed, expedient for the ordinary use of language, but has had unfortunate
consequences in metaphysics. Here the conditioning by everyday language has led to
confusions of types which, unlike those in everyday language, are no longer translatable into
logically correct form. Pseudo-statements of this kind are encountered in especially large
quantity, e.g., in the writings of Hegel and Heidegger. The latter has adopted many peculiarities
of the Hegelian idiom along with their logical faults (e.g. predicates which should be applied to
objects of a certain sort are instead applied to predicates of these objects or to "being" or to
"existence" or to a relation between these objects).
Having found that many metaphysical statements are meaningless, we confront the question
whether there is not perhaps a core of meaningful statements in metaphysics which would
remain after elimination of all the meaningless ones. Indeed, the results we have obtained so far
might give rise to the view that there are many dangers of falling into nonsense in metaphysics,
and that one must accordingly endeavor to avoid these traps with great care if one wants to do
metaphysics. But actually the situation is that meaningful metaphysical statements are
impossible. This follows from the task which metaphysics sets itself: to discover and formulate
a kind of knowledge which is not accessible to empirical science.
We have seen earlier that the meaning of a statement lies in the method of its verification. A
statement asserts only so much as is verifiable with respect to it. Therefore a sentence can be
used only to assert an empirical proposition, if indeed it is used to assert anything at all. If
something were to lie, in principle, beyond possible experience, it could be neither said nor
thought nor asked.
(Meaningful) statements are divided into the following kinds. First there are statements which
are true solely by virtue of their form ("tautologies" according to Wittgenstein; they correspond
approximately to Kant's "analytic judgments"). They say nothing about reality. The formulae of
logic and mathematics are of this kind. They are not themselves factual statements, but serve
for the transformation of such statements. Secondly there are the negations of such statements
("contradictions"). They are self-contradictory, hence false by virtue of their form. With respect
to all other statements the decision about truth or falsehood lies in the protocol sentences. They
are therefore (true or false) empirical statements and belong to the domain of empirical science.

Page 13
Any statement one desires to construct which does not fall within these categories becomes
automatically meaningless. Since metaphysics does not want to assert analytic propositions, nor
to fall within the domain of empirical science, it is compelled to employ words for which no
criteria of application are specified and which are therefore devoid of sense, or else to combine
meaningful words in such a way that neither an analytic (or contradictory) statement nor an
empirical statement is produced. In either case pseudo-statements are the inevitable product.
Logical analysis, then, pronounces the verdict of meaninglessness on any alleged knowledge
that pretends to reach above or behind experience. This verdict hits, in the first place, any
speculative metaphysics, any alleged knowledge by pure thinking or by pure intuition that
pretends to be able to do without experience. But the verdict equally applies to the kind of
metaphysics which, starting from experience, wants to acquire knowledge about that which
transcends experience by means of special inferences (e.g. the neo-vitalist thesis of the
directive presence of an "entelechy" in organic processes, which supposedly cannot be
understood in terms of physics; the question concerning the "essence of causality,"
transcending the ascertainment of certain regularities of succession; the talk about the "thing in
itself"). Further, the same judgment must be passed on all philosophy of norms, or philosophy
of value, on any ethics or esthetics as a normative discipline. For the objective validity of a
value or norm is (even on the view of the philosophers of value) not empirically verifiable nor
deducible from empirical statements; hence it cannot be asserted (in a meaningful statement) at
all. In other words: Either empirical criteria are indicated for the use of "good" and "beautiful"
and the rest of the predicates that are employed in the normative sciences, or they are not. In
the first case, a statement containing such a predicate turns into a factual judgment, but not a
value judgment; in the second case, it becomes a pseudo-statement. It is altogether impossible
to make a statement that expresses a value judgment.
Finally, the verdict of meaninglessness also hits those metaphysical movements which are
usually called, improperly, epistemological movements, that is realism (insofar as it claims to
say more than the empirical fact that the sequence of events exhibits a certain regularity, which
makes the application of the inductive method possible) and its opponents: subjective idealism,
solipsism, phenomenalism, and positivism (in the earlier sense).
But what, then, is left over for philosophy, if all statements whatever that assert something are
of an empirical nature and belong to factual science? What remains is not statements, nor a
theory, nor a system, but only a method: the method of logical analysis. The foregoing
discussion has illustrated the negative application of this method: in that context it serves to
eliminate meaningless words, meaningless pseudo-statements. In its positive use it serves to
clarify meaningful concepts and propositions, to lay logical foundations for factual science and
for mathematics. The negative application of the method is necessary and important in the
present historical situation. But even in its present practice, the positive application is more
fertile. We cannot here discuss it in greater detail. It is the indicated task of logical analysis,
inquiry into logical foundations, that is meant by "scientific philosophy" in contrast to
metaphysics.
The question regarding the logical character of the statements which we obtain as the result of a
logical analysis, e.g. the statements occurring in this and other logical papers, can here be
answered only tentatively: such statements are partly analytic, partly empirical. For these
statements about statements and parts of statements belong in part to pure metalogic (e.g. "a
sequence consisting of the existence-symbol and a noun, is not a sentence"), in part to
descriptive metalogic (e.g. "the word sequence at such and such a place in such and such a

Page 14
book is meaningless"). Metalogic will be discussed elsewhere. It will also be shown there that
the metalogic which speaks about the sentences of a given language can be formulated in that
very language itself.
7. METAPHYSICS AS EXPRESSION OF AN ATTITUDE
TOWARD LIFE
Our claim that the statements of metaphysics are entirely meaningless, that they do not assert
anything, will leave even those who agree intellectually with our results with a painful feeling
of strangeness: how could it be explained that so many men in all ages and nations, among
them eminent minds, spent so much energy, nay veritable fervor, on metaphysics if the latter
consisted of nothing but mere words, nonsensically juxtaposed? And how could one account
for the fact that metaphysical books have exerted such a strong influence on readers up to the
present day, if they contained not even errors, but nothing at all? These doubts are justified
since metaphysics does indeed have a content; only it is not theoretical content. The (pseudo)
statements of metaphysics do not serve for the description of states of affairs, neither existing
ones (in that case they would be true statements) nor non-existing ones (in that case they would
be at least false statements). They serve for the expression of the general attitude of a person
towards life ("Lebenseinstellung, Lebensgefühl").
Perhaps we may assume that metaphysics originated from mythology. The child is angry at the
"wicked table" which hurt him. Primitive man endeavors to conciliate the threatening demon of
earthquakes, or he worships the deity of the fertile rains in gratitude. Here we confront
personifications of natural phenomena, which are the quasi-poetic expression of man's
emotional relationship to his environment. The heritage of mythology is bequeathed on the one
hand to poetry, which produces and intensifies the effects of mythology on life in a deliberate
way; on the other hand, it is handed down to theology, which develops mythology into a
system. Which, now, is the historical role of metaphysics? Perhaps we may regard it as a
substitute for theology on the level of systematic, conceptual thinking. The (supposedly)
transcendent sources of knowledge of theology are here replaced by natural, yet supposedly
trans-empirical sources of knowledge. On closer inspection the same content as that of
mythology is here still recognizable behind the repeatedly varied dressing: we find that
metaphysics also arises from the need to give expression to a man's attitude in life, his
emotional and volitional reaction to the environment, to society, to the tasks to which he
devotes himself, to the misfortunes that befall him. This attitude manifests itself, unconsciously
as a rule, in everything a man does or says. It also impresses itself on his facial features,
perhaps even on the character of his gait. Many people, now, feel a desire to create over and
above these manifestations a special expression of their attitude, through which it might
become visible in a more succinct and penetrating way. If they have artistic talent they are able
to express themselves by producing a work of art. Many writers have already clarified the way
in which the basic attitude is manifested through the style and manner of a work of art (e.g.
Dilthey and his students). [In this connection the term "world view" ("Weltanschauung") is
often used; we prefer to avoid it because of its ambiguity, which blurs the difference between
attitude and theory, a difference which is of decisive importance for our analysis.] What is here
essential for our considerations is only the fact that art is an adequate, metaphysics an
inadequate means for the expression of the basic attitude. Of course, there need be no intrinsic
objection to one's using any means of expression one likes. But in the case of metaphysics we
find this situation: through the form of its works it pretends to be something that it is not. The
form in question is that of a system of statements which are apparently related as premises and
conclusions, that is, the form of a theory. In this way the fiction of theoretical content is

Page 15
generated, whereas, as we have seen, there is no such content. It is not only the reader, but the
metaphysician himself who suffers from the illusion that the metaphysical statements say
something, describe states of affairs. The metaphysician believes that he travels in territory in
which truth and falsehood are at stake. In reality, however, he has not asserted anything, but
only expressed something, like an artist. That the metaphysician is thus deluding himself
cannot be inferred from the fact that he selects language as the medium of expression and
declarative sentences as the form of expression; for lyrical poets do the same without
succumbing to self-delusion. But the metaphysician supports his statements by arguments, he
claims assent to their content, he polemicizes against metaphysicians of divergent persuasion
by attempting to refute their assertions in his treatise. Lyrical poets, on the other hand, do not
try to refute in their poem the statements in a poem by some other lyrical poet; for they know
they are in the domain of art and not in the domain of theory.Perhaps music is the purest means
of expression of the basic attitude because it is entirely free from any reference to objects. The
harmonious feeling or attitude, which the metaphysician tries to express in a monistic system, is
more clearly expressed in the music of Mozart. And when a metaphysician gives verbal
expression to his dualistic-heroic attitude towards life in a dualistic system, is it not perhaps
because he lacks the ability of a Beethoven to express this attitude in an adequate medium?
Metaphysicians are musicians without musical ability. Instead they have a strong inclination to
work within the medium of the theoretical, to connect concepts and thoughts. Now, instead of
activating, on the one hand, this inclination in the domain of science, and satisfying, on the
other hand, the need for expression in art, the metaphysician confuses the two and produces a
structure which achieves nothing for knowledge and something inadequate for the expression
of attitude.Our conjecture that metaphysics is a substitute, albeit an inadequate one, for art,
seems to be further confirmed by the fact that the metaphysician who perhaps had artistic talent
to the highest degree, viz. Nietzsche, almost entirely avoided the error of that confusion. A
large part of his work has predominantly empirical content. We find there, for instance,
historical analyses of specific artistic phenomena, or an historical-psychological analysis of
morals. In the work, however, in which he expresses most strongly that which others express
through metaphysics or ethics, in Thus Spake Zarathustra, he does not choose the misleading
theoretical form, but openly the form of art, of poetry.
REMARKS BY THE AUTHOR ( 1957)
To section 1, "metaphysics." This term is used in this paper, as usually in Europe, for the
field of alleged knowledge of the essence of things which transcends the realm of
empirically founded, inductive science. Metaphysics in this sense includes systems like those
of Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Bergson, Heidegger. But it does not include endeavors towards a
synthesis and generalization of the results of the various sciences.
To section 1, "meaning." Today we distinguish various kinds of meaning, in particular
cognitive (designative, referential) meaning on the one hand, and non-cognitive (expressive)
meaning components, e.g. emotive and motivative, on the other. In the present paper, the
word "meaning" is always understood in the sense of "cognitive meaning." The thesis that
the sentences of metaphysics are meaningless, is thus to be understood in the sense that they
have no cognitive meaning, no assertive content. The obvious psychological fact that they
have expressive meaning is thereby not denied; this is explicitly stated in Section 7.
To section 6, "metalogic." This term refers to the theory of expressions of a language and,
in particular, of their logical relations. Today we would distinguish between logical syntax as
the theory of purely formal relations and semantics as the theory of meaning and
truthconditions.
To section 6, realism and idealism. That both the affirmative and the negative theses
concerning the reality of the external world are pseudostatements, I have tried to show in the

Page 16
monograph Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie: Das Fremdpsychische und der
Realismusstreit, Berlin, 1928. The similar nature of the ontological theses about the reality
or unreality of abstract entities, e.g., properties, relations, propositions, is discussed in
"Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology", Revue Intern. de Philos. 4, 1950, 20-40, reprinted
in: Meaning and Necessity, second edition, Chicago, 1956.